The Philosophy Of Schizophrenia Essay, Research Paper
Phil-229
Trinity College
In his book, The Paradoxes of Delusion, Louis Sass attempts to rebut two of most
prevalent beliefs of the schizophrenic person. He argues that by viewing the
schizophrenic delusions in light of solipsism, a philosophy of existence, the
schizophrenic may seem far more understandable. Through his comparison of the
schizophrenic and solipsist realities, Sass explains that not only is schizophrenia
understandable, but that there exists within the structure of schizophrenic delusion a
seemingly self-contradictory state which in actuality approximates a sort of logic more
than anything else. Thus, according to Sass, schizophrenia should not be deemed a state
of unreason, but rather a reason which results from a dual conceptualization of the
reality.
Sass first introduces the traditional understanding of madness and delusion. The
most fundamental basis under which a person is diagnosed as insane is when he displays
a poor of false understanding of his environment, called ?poor reality testing.?
?…disturbance in or failure of ?reality-testing? is considered to be the defining criterion
for diagnosing a so called psychotic condition.?(p.1) The inability to correctly perceive
reality is considered to be the basis for delusion, the basic characteristic of madness. But,
as Sass explains, patients with schizophrenia, ?the most severe and paradigmatic kind of
insanity,? often do not display actual poor reality-testing.
While schizophrenic patients tend to accord great importance to their delusions,
they do not handle said delusions in the same way that they handle what they understand
to be objective reality. ?…many schizophrenics who seem to be profoundly preoccupied
with their delusions…treat these same beliefs with what seems a certain distance and
irony.?(p.20-21) They seem to retain two understandings of reality, so called ?double
bookkeeping,? which allows them to exist ?in two parallel but separate worlds:
consensual reality and the realm of their hallucinations…?(p.21) This concept helps to
explain why many schizophrenic patients do not act on their delusions in a manner which
is appropriate for the given delusional situation. ?A patient who claims that the doctors
and nurses are trying to torture and poison her may nevertheless happily consume the
food they give her.?(p.21) They believe that their delusions are real, but only in the
context of a world known only to them. ?Schreber insists…that such beliefs-he calls
them ?my so-called delusions?-refers to a separate realm, one that does not motivate him
to act and wherein the usual criteria of worldly proof does not apply.?(p.31)
While common understandings of poor reality testing include a patient?s belief in
things which are objectively false or non-existent, Sass argues that many schizophrenics
also disbelieve those things which can be deemed objectively true or real. ?…often
schizophrenic delusions involve not belief in the unreal but disbelief in something that
most people take to be true. Schizophrenic patients may..speak disbelievingly of ?my
so-called children and this so-called hospital…?(p.24) Along with these ?delusions of
disbelief,? schizophrenic patients may perceive other human beings as machines or
phantoms which just seem to be real people.
Sass also explains how schizophrenic patients may believe that many of their
experiences are products of their own mind and consciousness, as if they have created the
reality which surrounds them by their own thought. ?Schizophrenics may believe that
they have invented everything they encounter-that…they themselves have just invented
the story they have just read?(p.22) Schreber believed that the insects he saw were
created at the moment he looked at them, and disappeared as soon as he looked away.
These examples, along with the schizophrenic suspicion concerning the reality of other
human beings, are central to Sass? likening of schizophrenia to the philosophical notion
of solipsism.
A solipsist believes that his reality is the only true reality, or as Wittgenstein puts
it, ?The world is my idea.?(p.34) Most basically, solipsism refers to the belief that
everything one perceives is a product of his own mind. Like the schizophrenic, the
solipsist views other people as phantoms of a sort. ?For the solipsist, other people, other
seeming centers of consciousness, are but dream personages, figments of the solipsist?s
own conscious activity and awareness.?(p.34) Because the most basic tenets of solipsism
are lived out in the schizophrenic delusions, Sass believes that by considering the
symptoms of schizophrenia in light of the solipsist model of reality, we can gain an
understanding of much of the schizophrenic condition.
Sass explains that Wittgenstein saw a strong connection between solipsism and
intense concentration or ?staring.? ?The phenomenon of staring is closely bound up with
the whole puzzle of solipsism.?(p.35) Wittgenstein also noted the importance of
inactivity to the solipsist experience. Sass explains that by interacting with and moving
about the world, a person has no choice but to accept the physical and objective quality
of everything around him. This recognition ?precludes a sense of…subjectivization?
(p.35) thus hindering the solipsist understanding that everything he sees is, in effect, a
product of his own mind.
By interacting with the world..one is obliged to recognize
the world?s otherness…in a passive state, the world may
look rather different. The more one stares at things, the
more they may seem to have a coefficient of subjectivity;
the more they may come to seem ?things seen.? When
staring fixedly ahead, the field of consciousness as such
can come into prominence; then, it is as if the lens of
awareness were clouding over and the world beyond were
taking on the aphanous quality of a dream. At this point,
the person can be said to experience experience rather than
the world…(pp.35-36)
This is to say that the longer we stare at something, the more we think of a certain object
in the sense of a visual, rather than physical object. Viewed as the concept of an object
rather than an object in and of itself, the thing takes on a highly subjective quality. ?In
this situation, any object of awareness tends to feel that it depends on me in some special
way, belonging to my consciousness as a private and somehow inner possession.?(p.36)
Sass points out that many of Schreber?s schizophrenic experiences were
accompanied by just such circumstances of intense concentration and almost complete
inactivity. ?Apart from daily morning and afternoon walks in the garden, I mainly sat
motionless the whole day on a chair at my table…?(p.37) It appears that certain types of
delusions would not occur if Schreber were moving around. ?The experience of
?miracled-up? insects…seems not to have occurred unless Schreber was in a state of
immobility…if he sat down and waited he could actually provoke this wasp miracle.?
(p.38)
Schreber?s experience of the ?wasp-miracle? is perhaps the very best example of
the proximity of the schizophrenic and solipsist realms. He believed that his gaze
provoked the spontaneous generation of the insects, an understanding which gave
Schreber the ?sense of being the conscious center before whom and for whom events
appear.?(p.38) Sass also points out passages of Schreber?s Memoirs which indicate his
awareness that other minds cannot exist, a fundamental notion of solipsism. ?The
solipsist, who is so struck with the undeniable actuality and centrality of his own
experience, obviously cannot have this same awareness of the experience of others. In
fact, the more he pays attention to his own experience, the more unlikely it seems that
other people can have anything like this-and the more others come to seem…not really
conscious beings at all.?(p.39)
An understanding of solipsism helps us to see why the schizophrenic patients fail
to respond to their delusions or react in what seems an inappropriate manner. As Sass
explains, both schizophrenics and solipsists see reality as a mental reality of concepts or
ideas. Thus is would be largely futile to attempt to act out in any physical way because
tangible maneuvers could have no affect in a world where nothing is of substance. ?…in
a solipsistic universe, to act might feel either unnecessary or impossible: unnecessary
because external conditions are at the mercy of thought…impossible because real action,
action in a world able to resist my efforts, cannot occur in a purely mental universe.?
(p.42) In light of this ?merely mental or representation? understanding of the world, it
seems clear that a schizophrenic person would naturally speak in metaphor, something
which Sass believes is often unknown or ignored. ?A failure to realize that a patient may
be describing such a mode of experience can…lead to an overly literal interpretation by
the therapist, and thus the mistaken impression that the patient?s reality testing has
broken down.?(p.44) Additionally, schizophrenic patients often perceive their own
physical bodies as representational or conceptual. So when they have delusions of their
bodies and other people?s bodies undergoing radical physical changes, they are not
bothered by it because it seems affectless and inconsequential, as if one were cutting up
paper dolls.
Sass explains that consideration of the solipsist reality can illustrate a potential
reason for the schizophrenic anxiety, described by a doctor of Schreber?s as a ?tense? and
?irritable? state ?caused by inner uneasiness.?(p.37) With the belief that the world is a
product of one?s own mind comes, to a schizophrenic patient, an immense feeling of
responsibility. They lack the luxury of having the ability to ?stop playing the game,? if
you will, and leave their beliefs behind. While the notion of single-handedly controlling
existence is accompanied by a sense of awesome power, it also proceeds a fear of
causing the demise of the universe. ?One catatonic patient explained why she would
hold herself immobile for hours in an uncomfortable position…it was, she said, for the
purpose of ?stopping the world march to catastrophe?: ?If I succeed in remaining in a
perfect state of suspension, I will suspend the movement of the earth and stop the march
of the world to destruction.??(p.50)
Wittgenstein believes, and rightfully so, that solipsism is wrought with
contradiction. Sass also admits that schizophrenic patients are often plagued by their
own contradictions, most notably simultaneous feelings of omnipotence and impotence,
and the desire to make others understand their experience while believing that they are
the only people capable of experience. Many of these contradictory notions do not work
within the context of the solipsist world view, and thus appear at first to work against
Sass? crucial comparison between schizophrenia and solipsism. However, Sass proposes
that the contradictory nature of the schizophrenic experience does not undermine its
close relation to solipsism, but rather demonstrates the proximity of schizophrenia to the
inherently contradictory nature of solipsism itself.
Schizophrenics typically oscillate persistently between a feeling of being a virtual
master of the universe and a belief that their very being is in some way inconsequential.
?Schreber senses at times that his boundaries extend to the ends of the universe: ?It
appeared that nerves-probably taken from my body-were strung over the whole heavenly
vault.? But he also feels that he is tiny, and almost nonexistent being lost in the vastness
of space.?(p.65) While the latter may seem to contradict Sass? link between the
schizophrenic delusional world and the solipsist understanding of reality, Sass explains
that if we simply follow Wittgenstein?s argument against the solipsistic viewpoint, we
see that even in self contradiction, the schizophrenic reality may maintain it?s close
connection with solipsism. A solipsist begins by believing in his central, controlling role
of the universe. Staring and intense concentration give a person the feeling that ?only me
experience of the present moment is real.?(p.67) But, as Wittgenstein explains, if a
person follows the solipsist principles carefully, he will soon realize that he is does not
see himself in his existence, even though his experience is all that really is. ?If he closely
scrutinizes his experiences-which…are all that exists-he must admit that he does not find
himself there.?
He goes further to say that if a solipsist did see himself in his world, it could only
be as an object of that world, which is, in affect, a product of thoughts and ideas. He
cannot, from this experience, affirm his omnipotence. ?…even if one did see oneself
within one?s experience, that self, being within the phenomenal field, could exist only as
an object, not in the role of the all powerful constituting subjectivity for which the
solipsist yearns…?(p.68) Furthermore, since the solipsist believe the only reality is that
which is perceived, and since he cannot perceive himself as anything but an object of his
own consciousness, it is necessary for the solipsist to believe there is another conscious
being which perceives him as an object, thus confirming his object reality. But this
concession also undermines the primary tenet of his reality being the only reality.
With all of this in mind, it seems clear that the schizophrenic patients could
understandably feel both all and nothing at the same time. In Schreber?s case, Sass
points out, his ?sense of being the solipsistic center occurred at those moments when he
was also experiencing the contradictory presence of another mind.?(p.73) The ?one?
whom Schreber speaks of so frequently is generally a believer in the idea that Schreber
creates the world around him. This also gives insight into the typical schizophrenic ?loss
of self,? that is, the felling that one?s thoughts are belong to some other consciousness or
no one at all. This could also be related to the feeling which schizophrenics have of
some foreign power controlling the direction of their gaze.
By demonstrating that schizophrenia mirrors a philosophic notion like solipsism,
Sass successfully illustrates that it is not entirely accurate to believe in schizophrenia as a
state of unreason. While one might correctly state that solipsism is in some way illogical
and unreasonable in and of itself, it would be still be reasonable to conclude that there is
some inherent logic or reason in the discovery of this inherent self-contradiction. If
something is self-contradicting by nature, it is logical to conclude that this is illogical,
and thus we should not view schizophrenia as unreason because there is a sort of logic to
its illogical nature. Within the context of solipsism, it makes perfect, logical sense that a
person should feel almighty and powerless at the same time. It would seem then, that
schizophrenia is, in a sense, the illogic of solipsism taken to it?s logical conclusion.
Part of the reason Sass? conclusion makes so much sense is the simple fact that
much of what the schizophrenics do does not look or sound like unreason, but rather like
a preoccupation or obsession with reason itself. They constantly examine and scrutinize
every aspect of themselves and their existence. They do mental checks and rechecks to
make sure they are actually participating in the activity which they believe they are.
They overanalyze every aspect of normal human processes and nature, and search for the
reason and explanation behind every twitch and jitter, every sound their body makes.
Their mode of though is not unreason but over-reason, in which they often concentrate on
one object for so long that it begins to take on a surreal quality within a person?s own
mind. As Sass points out, ?it is significant that schizophrenic patients often do report
that performing some action or interaction with others makes their odd perceptual
experiences disappear-that when they comb their hair or shovel snow…the world turns
normal again, at least for a time.?(p.113) This suggests that when a schizophrenic person
removes himself from the passive world, he has the ability to stop the delusions-the
delusions are at least partially a result of over analysis of the consensual world. Schreber
tries to escape this world of ?compulsive thinking,? but cannot.
We must also take into consideration another important aspect of schizophrenia