Смекни!
smekni.com

Adam Smith Essay Research Paper Adam Smith (стр. 1 из 2)

Adam Smith Essay, Research Paper

Adam Smith

Adam Smith, a brilliant eighteenth-century Scottish political economist, had the advantage of judging the significance ol colonies by a rigorous examination based on the colonial experience of 300 years. His overview has a built-in bias: he strongly disapproved of excessive regulation of colonial trade by parent countries. But his analysis is rich with insight and remarkably dispassionate in its argument. Adam Smith recognized that the discovery of the New World not only brought wealth and prosperity to the Old World, but that it also marked a divide in the history of mankind. The passage that follows is the work of this economic theorist who discusses problems in a language readily understandable by everyone.

Adam Smith had retired from a professorship at Glasgow University and Was living in France in 1764-5 when he began his great work, The Wealth of Nations. The book was being written all during the years of strife between Britain and her colonies, but it was not published until 1776. In the passages which follow, Smith points to the impossibility of monopolizing the benefits of colonies, and pessimistically calculates the cost of empire, but the book appeared too late to have any effect upon British policy. Because the Declaration of Independence and The Wealth of Nations, the political and economic reliations of empire and mercantilism, appeared in the same year, historians have often designated 1776 as one of the turning points in modern history. The text On the cost of Empire, the eloquent exhortation to the rulers of Britain to awaken from their grandiose dreams of empire, is the closing passage of Smith’s book.

Adam Smith was a Scottish political economist and philosopher. He has become famous by his influential book The Wealth of Nations (1776). Smith was the son of the comptroller of the customs at Kirkcaldy, Fife, Scotland. The exact date of his birth is unknown. However, he was baptized at Kirkcaldy on June 5, 1723, his father having died some six months previously.

At the age of about fifteen, Smith proceeded to Glasgow university, studying moral philosophy under “the never-to-be-forgotten” Francis Hutcheson (as Smith called him). In 1740 he entered Balliol college, Oxford, but as William Robert Scott has said, “the Oxford of his time gave little if any help towards what was to be his lifework,” and he relinquished his exhibition in 1746. In 1748 he began delivering public lectures in Edinburgh under the patronage of Lord Kames. Some of these dealt with rhetoric and belles-lettres, but later he took up the subject of “the progress of opulence,” and it was then, in his middle or late 20s, that he first expounded the economic philosophy of “the obvious and simple system of natural liberty” which he was later to proclaim to the world in his Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. About 1750 he met David Hume, who became one of the closest of his many friends.

In 1751 Smith was appointed professor of logic at Glasgow university, transferring in 1752 to the chair of moral philosophy. His lectures covered the field of ethics, rhetoric, jurisprudence and political economy, or “police and revenue.” In 1759 he published his Theory of Moral Sentiments, embodying some of his Glasgow lectures. This work, which established Smith’s reputation in his own day, is concerned with the explanation of moral approval and disapproval. His capacity for fluent, persuasive, if rather rhetorical argument is much in evidence. He bases his explanation, not as the third Lord Shaftesbury and Hutcheson had done, on a special “moral sense,”nor, like Hume, to any decisive extent on utility,but on sympathy. There has been considerable controversy as how far there is contradiction or contrast between Smith’s emphasis in the Moral Sentiments on sympathy as a fundamental human motive, and, on the other hand, the key role of self-interest in the The Wealth of Nations. In the former he seems to put more emphasis on the general harmony of human motives and activities under a beneficent Providence, while in the latter, in spite of the general theme of “the invisible hand” promoting the harmony of interests, Smith finds many more occasions for pointing out cases of conflict and of the narrow selfishness of human motives.

Smith now began to give more attention to jurisprudence and political economy in his lecture and less to his theories of morals. An impression can be obtained as to the development of his ideas on political economy from the notes of his lectures taken down by a student in about 1763 which were later edited by E. Cannan (Lectures on Justice, Police, Revenue and Arms,1896), and from what Scott, its discoverer and publisher, describes as “An Early Draft of Part of The Wealth of Nations, which he dates about 1763.

At the end of 1763 Smith obtained a lucrative post as tutor to the young duke of Buccleuch and resigned his professorship. From 1764-66 he traveled with his pupil, mostly in France, where he came to know such intellectual leaders as Turgot, D’Alembert, Andr?Morellet, Helv?tius and, in particular, Francois Quesnay, the head of the Physiocratic school whose work he much respected. On returning home to Kirkcaldy he devoted much of the next ten years to his magnum opus, which appeared in 1776. In 1778 he was appointed to a comfortable post as commissioner of customs in Scotland and went to live with his mother in Edinburgh. He died there on July 17, 1790, after a painfull illness. He had apparently devoted a considerable part of his income to numerous secret acts of charity.

Shortly before his death Smith had nearly all his manuscripts destroyed. In his last years he seems to have been planning two major treatises, one on the theory and history of law and one on the sciences and arts. The posthumously published Essays on Philosophical Subjects (1795) probably contain parts of what would have been the latter treatise.

The Wealth of Nations has become so influential since it did so much to create the subject of political economy and develop it into an autonomous systematic discipline. In the western world, it is the most influential book on the subject ever published. When the book, which has become a classic manifesto against mercantalism, appeared in 1776, there was a strong sentiment for free trade in both Britain and America. This new feeling had been born out of the economic hardships and poverty caused by the war. However, at the time of publication, not everybody was convinced of the advantages of free trade right away: the British public and Parliament still clung to mercantilism for many years to come (Tindall and Shi). However, controversial views have been expressed as to the extent of Smith’s originality in The Wealth of Nations. Smith has been blamed for relying too much on the ideas of great thinkers such as David Hume and Montesquieu. Nevertheless, The Wealth of Nations was the first and remains the most important book on the subject of political ecomomy until this present day.

It has never, I think, been the good fortune of any founder

of a scientific system to think out to the very end even the more

important ideas that constitute his system. The strength and

lifetime of no single man are sufficient for that. It is enough

if some few of the ideas which have to play the chief part in the

system are put on a perfectly safe foundation, and analysed in

all their ramifications and complexities. It is a great deal if,

over and above that, an equal carefulness falls to the lot of a

few other favoured members of the system. But in all cases the

most ambitious spirit must be content to build up a great deal

that is insecure, and to fit into his system, on cursory

examination, ideas which it was not permitted him to work out.

We must keep these considerations before us if we would

rightly appreciate Adam Smith’s attitude towards our problem.

Adam Smith has not overlooked the problem of interest;

neither has he worked it out. He deals with it as a great thinker

may deal with an important subject which he often comes across,

but has not time or opportunity to go very deeply into. He has

adopted a certain proximate but still vague explanation. The more

indefinite this explanation is, the less does it bind him to

strict conclusions; and a many-sided mind like Adam Smith’s,

seeing all the many different ways in which the problem can be

put, but lacking the control which the possession of a distinct

theory gives, could scarcely fail to fall into all sorts of

wavering and contradictory expressions. Thus we have the peculiar

phenomenon that, while Adam Smith has not laid down any distinct

theory of interest, the germs of almost all the later and

conflicting theories are to be found, with more or less

distinctness, in his scattered observations. We find the same

phenomenon in Adam Smith as regards many other questions.

The line of thought which seems to commend itself principally

to him as explaining natural interest occurs in very similar

language in the sixth and eighth chapters of book i of the Wealth

of Nations. It amounts to this, that there must be a profit from

capital, because otherwise the capitalist would have no interest

in spending his capital in the productive employment of

labourers.(1*)

General expressions like these have of course no claim to

stand for a complete theory.(2*) There is no reasoned attempt in

them to show what we are to represent as the actual connecting

links between the psychological motive of the capitalist’s

self-interest and the final fixing of market prices which leave a

difference between costs and proceeds that we call interest. But

yet, if we take those expressions in connection with a later

passage,(3*) where Smith sharply opposes the “future profit” that

rewards the resolution of the capitalist to the “present

enjoyment” of immediate consumption, we may recognise the first

germs of that theory which Senior worked out later on under the

name of the Abstinence theory.

In the same way as Adam Smith asserts the necessity of

interest, and leaves it without going any deeper in the way of

proof, so does he avoid making any systematic investigation of

the important question of the source of undertaker’s profit. He

contents himself with making a few passing observations on the

subject. Indeed in different places he gives two contradictory

accounts of this profit. According to one account, the profit of

capital arises from the circumstance, that, to meet the

capitalist’s claim to profit, buyers have to submit to pay

something more for their goods than the value which these goods

would get from the labour expended on them. according to this

explanation, the source of interest is an increased value given

to the product over that value which labour creates; but no

explanation of this increase in value is given. According to the

second account, interest is a deduction which the capitalist

makes in his own favour from the return to labour, so that the

workers do not receive the full value created by them, but are

obliged to share it with the capitalist. According to this

account, profit is a part of the value created by labour and kept

back by capital.

Both accounts are to be found in a great number of passages;

and these passages, oddly enough, sometimes stand quite close to

each other, as, e.g. in the sixth chapter of the first book.

Adam Smith has been speaking in that chapter of a past time,

– of course a mythical time, — when the land was not yet

appropriated, and when an accumulation of capital had not yet

begun, and has made the remark that, at that time, the quantity

of labour required for the production of goods would be the sole

determinant of their price. He continues: “As soon as stock has

accumulated in the hands of particular persons, some of them will

naturally employ it in setting to work industrious people, whom

they will supply with materials and subsistence, in order to make

a profit by the sale of their work, or by what their labour adds

to the value of the materials. In exchanging the complete

manufacture either for money, for labour, or for other goods,

over and above what may be sufficient to pay the price of the

materials and the wages of the workmen, something must be given

for the profits of the undertaker of the work, who hazards his

stock in this adventure.”

This sentence, when taken with the opposite remark of the

previous paragraph (that, in primitive conditions, labour is the

sole determinant of price), very clearly expresses the opinion

that the capitalist’s claim of interest causes a rise in the

price of the product, and is met from this raised price. But Adam

Smith immediately goes on to say: “The value which the workman

adds to the material, therefore, resolves itself in this case

into two parts, of which the one pays the wages, the other the

profits of the employer upon the whole stock of materials and

wages which he advanced.” Here again the price of the product is

looked upon as exclusively determined by the quantity of labour

expended, and the claim of interest is said to be met by a part

of the return which the worker has produced.

We meet the same contradiction, put even more strikingly, a

page farther on.

“In this state of things,” says Adam Smith, “the whole

produce of labour does not always belong to the labourer. He must

in most cases share it with the owner of the stock which employs

him.” This is an evident paraphrase of the second account. But

immediately after that come the words: “Neither is the quantity

of labour commonly employed in acquiring or producing any

commodity, the only circumstance which can regulate the quantity

which it ought commonly to purchase, command, or exchange for. An

additional quantity, it is evident, must be due for the profits

of the stock which advanced the wages and furnished the materials

of that labour.” He could scarcely have said more plainly that

the effect of a claim of interest is to raise prices without

curtailing the wages of labour.

Later on he says alternately: “As in a civilised community

there are but few commodities of which the exchangeable value

arises from labour only, rent and profit contributing largely to

that of the far greater part of them, so the annual produce of

its labour will always be sufficient to purchase or command a

much greater quantity of labour than was employed in raising,

preparing, and bringing that produce to market” (first account,

chap. vi.) “The produce of almost all other labour is liable to

the like deduction of profit. In all arts and manufactures the

greater part of the workmen stand in need of a master to advance

them the materials of their work, and their wages and maintenance

till it be completed. He shares in the produce of their labour,

or in the value which it adds to the materials upon which it is

bestowed; and in this consists his profit” (second account, chap.

viii.)

“High or low wages and profit are the causes of high or low

price; high or low rent is the effect of it” (first account,

chap. xi.)

Contradictions like these on the part of such an eminent

thinker admit, I think, of only one explanation; — that Adam

Smith had not thoroughly thought out the interest problem; and –

as is usual with those who have only imperfectly mastered a

subject — was not very particular in his choice of expressions,

but allowed himself to be swayed very much by the changing

impressions which the subject may have made on him from time to

time.

Adam Smith, then, has no perfected theory of interest.(4*)

But the suggestions he threw out were all destined to fall on

fruitful soil. His casual remark on the necessity of interest was

developed later into the Abstinence theory. In the same way the

two accounts he gave of the source of interest were taken up by

his followers, logically carried out, and raised into principles

of independent theories. With the first account — that interest

is paid out of an additional value which the employment of

capital calls into existence — are connected the later

Productivity theories. With the second account — that interest

is paid out of the return to labour — are connected the

Socialist theories of interest. Thus the most important of later

theories trace their pedigree back to Adam Smith.

The position taken by Adam Smith towards the question may be

called that of a complete neutrality. He is neutral in his

theoretical exposition, for he takes the germs of distinct

theories and puts them beside each other, without giving any one

of them a distinct prominence over the others. And he is neutral

in his practical judgment, for he maintains the same reserve, or